A case study on the conveyor belt metaphor in oceanography*
Foundations of Science, Special Issue for the International Congress on Discovery and Creativity in Gent, 4(4), 389-405.
Foundations of Science, Volume & Issue Summary
Reinhart Br?ning
Zurlaubener Ufer 83, D-54292 Trier, Germany,
Tel. +49(0)651-140701 Email:
bruening@bigfoot.de
Gerrit Lohmann
Max-Planck-Institute for Meteorology, Bundesstrasse 55, D-20146 Hamburg,
Germany,
phone: +49(0)40-41173103 fax: +49(0)40-41173298, email:
gerrit.lohmann@dkrz.de,
1 Abstract
Within Charles Sanders Peirce's semiotical theory, two different kinds of
creative metaphorical reasoning in science can be identified. One of these,
the building of remainder metaphors, is especially important for creating new
scientific models. We show that the conveyor belt metaphor provides an
excellent example for Peirce's theory. The conveyor belt metaphor has
recently been invented in order to describe the oceanic transport system. The
paradigm of the oceanic conveyor belt strongly influenced the geoscience
community and the climate change discussion.
Keywords: metaphor, creativity, heuristics, C. S. Peirce, oceanography
After identifying structures of metaphorical reasoning in science (section 2), these structures are examined in section 3 for the conveyor belt metaphor
in the field of oceanography. Finally, concluding remarks are given in
section 4.
2 Metaphors in science
Charles S. Peirce's triadic relation of signs provides a theory of metaphor
with a systematic background. The most important of his statements about
metaphor can be found in a covering note to the Lowell-Lectures from 1903.
"Hypoicons may be roughly divided according to the mode of Firstness of which
they partake. Those which partake of simple qualities, or First Firstnesses,
are images; those which represent the relations, mainly dyadic, or so
regarded, of the parts of one thing by analogous relations in their own
parts, are diagrams; those which represent the representative character of a
representamen by representing a parallelism in something else, are
metaphors."
By dividing a specific class of signs, the hypoicons , following according to
his three basic categories, he gets: image for the Firstness, diagram for the
Secondness and metaphor for the Thirdness. Peirce gives as an example of an
image predicate the proposition "Cain murders Abel". For a diagram predicate
he gives "A is like B" as a one-figure example and "A-B-... is like H-I-..."
as a many-figure example. But Peirce does not clearly describe what a
metaphor predicate could be. A metaphor should contain two qualities mediated by a third that is added by an interpretant. Following Christian Strub's interpretation of Peirce's text , metaphor describes the two qualities as a parallelism predicate that contains two parts: a diagram and a The diagrammed
subject and its diagram (analogous to the terminology of Black (1954) as
subsidiary and the principal subject and its subsidiary subject). For
instance, in the metaphor "The man is a wolf" wolf forms the diagram of the
diagrammed man.
A metaphor is in most cases literally an absurd proposition. This means that
it is a kind of irregularity that can be described in two ways. (I) The
metaphor seems to break the rules, but in the end is only an encoding of the
rules. In this case metaphor is a shorter way to express something that can
also be expressed literally. (II) The metaphor follows new rules that violate
the old rules. Such a description emphasizes the irreplaceability of metaphor
with literal descriptions. This class Black calls this class emphatical
metaphors. In this case we have something analogous but not identical to
everyday speech.
For both of these descriptions, two strategies exist to interpret a metaphor
as something sensible: (A) At the level of a term; or (B) at the level of a
sentence.
The result is four classes of metaphor:
(AI) The metaphorical term expresses another term that has a standard
meaning; or (AII) The metaphorical term does not have the standard meaning
but another meaning instead. The other two classes (BI) and (BII) describe
metaphor at the level of a sentence, whereby a new parameter for the sentence
is used to resolve the absurdity. The connection between terms rather than
the terms themselves is interpreted in a new way. The sentence is only absurd
because of a normal interpretation of this connection. Then we have: (BI) The
absurd sentence is transformed with words such as 'is like' or 'is as' into a
normal sentence. Here metaphor is an elliptical comparison. (BII) A special
metaphorical copula is introduced that contains the metaphorical aspect of
the predicate. Miller (1995, p. 201) uses this strategy when he standardizes
metaphor with the construction: "The term metaphor will be used as follows:
x behaves as if it were a y."
Only emphatical metaphors appear as creative metaphors in science. They
cannot be replaced by literal language. Following Peirce, we prefer the 'term
strategy' rather than the 'sentence strategy' for our description of metaphor
in science. Thus, we have a parallelism predicate instead of a parallelism
copula. Let's take an example from science: the metaphor "The atom is a solar
system." Following the term strategy this metaphor can be interpreted as a
parallelism predicate:
The atom is (an atom || a solar system).
The parallelism predicate contains no simple duplication of the subject
because in the first position 'atom' works as an index, and in the
parallelism predicate it describes a quality. The metaphor focuses attention
not only on the similarities between the qualities of 'atom' and 'solar
system', but especially on the differences. Pointing out the differences is
the very core of the irreplaceability of metaphor.
There are two kinds of emphatical metaphor in science: the stock metaphor;
and the remainder metaphor. Stock metaphors are emphatical because they can
never be replaced. In this case metaphor is the only way to describe terms
that can never be exemplified. Remainder metaphors are introduced in order to
be replaced later on. They are emphatical in that in the present they cannot
be replaced. Following Strub's interpretation of Peirce's metaphor theory
there are two possibilities in that which remainder metaphors can
prestructure and prepare the building of a model in science :
i. Deepening metaphor: the diagram of the parallelism predicate is less
complicated than its subject. Its simpler composition helps to structure the
subject by emphasizing special features of the complicated structure.
ii. Extension metaphor: in this case the diagram is richer than its
subject. It focuses on poor or unclear elements or parts of the diagrammed
subject.
How can remainder metaphors work in building scientific models? A metaphor
can complicate an old model M1 in science by pointing to dissimilarities. By
doing this it prepares a new model M2. One can divide this development into
three steps. First, on the basis of the old model an emphatical metaphor is
made. With the second step of conventionalizing the metaphor a new model is
established. This model metaphor further develops and in a third step is then
lexically proscribed. Now the predictive quality of the metaphor has
completely disappeared. All qualities of the model can be described literally
without using the metaphor. The metaphor remains only as a shorter more
concise way to express literal qualities, and as a reminder of the
developmental process used to achieve the new model.
3 The conveyor belt metaphor
In the following section, the different aspects of metaphor that have been
mentioned so far will be discussed in more detail. We shall present the
results of an historical case study from contemporary geoscience in that an
emphatical remainder metaphor plays an important role. This metaphor is
called the conveyer belt metaphor. It was created by Wallace S. Broecker , as
part of a model describing deep sea circulation in large scale oceanography.
A similar model was used by Arnold L. Gordon used a similar model in his work
that was not without publisheding it.
Before discussing three different historical steps of development of the
conveyor belt model we give a short historical introduction on deep sea
circulation models.
3.1 History of deep sea circulation models
In 1749 Henry Ellis, captain of a British slave trader, made the first
documented temperature measurements of deep ocean water in the open sea.
Though his measurements were quite inexact, they made clear that the Atlantic
has only a small top layer of warm surface water and the rest of the water is
colder. In 1797, the Count of Rumford was the first who explained Ellis' and
additional data. Starting with laboratory experiments, he developed an ocean
circulation model that was published under the title, "The Propagation of
Heat in Fluids" and was translated in several languages:
"But if the water of the ocean, which, on being deprived of a great part of
its Heat by cold winds, descends to the bottom of the sea, cannot be warmed
where it descends, as its specific gravity is greater than that of water at
the same depth in warmer latitudes, it will immediately begin to spread on
the bottom of the sea, and to flow towards the equator, and this must
necessarily produce a current at the surface in an opposite direction."
In 1814, Alexander v. Humboldt published a similar model in which heand
assumed that the ocean bottom water originates originated from polar regions.
This model was refined by the physicist Emil von Lenz. (Lenz, 1847a, b).
HeLenz described the first model of longitudinal circulation as consisting
of two big vortexes symmetrical to the equator (cf. Fig. 1).
Fig. 1: Atlantic circulation model according to (von Lenz, 1847a, b), figure
according to (Merz and W?st, 1922)
This structure explains why subtropical surface water is warmer than tropical
surface water in spite of the fact that the latter region receives more solar
radiation.
Detailed measurements of the Atlantic's current structure were made by an
expedition of the research vessel 'Meteor' from 1925-1927. On the basis of
these data, Georg WFCst (1935) characterized water masses necessary to
describe the Atlantic's currents and tracer distribution.
Wallace S. Broecker proposed a circulation model based on findings of the
Meteor and other world wide expeditions. In his model, large scale oceanic
circulation is represented by the transport system of a conveyor belt. In
Broecker's model, (cf. Fig. 2) the conveyor is driven by deepwater formation
in the northern North Atlantic, making itthat is the engine of the conveyor
belt circulation.
Broecker's concept provides a successful approach for global ocean
circulation.
Fig. 2: The great ocean conveyor logo (Broecker, 1987).
Warm and salty water entering the
north Atlantic region is cooled. The dense water formed at the surface is
convected to the deep ocean and is part of the southward return flow.
3.2 Three historical steps of the conveyor belt metaphor
Now the following three historical steps of Broecker's conveyor belt metaphor
are discussed:
I) conventionalized model metaphor1
II) model metaphor1 restored to life as emphatical remainder metaphor2
III) communication of the conventionalized model metaphor3
3.2.1 Step I) conventionalized model metaphor1
In 1982, the conveyor belt appeared for the first time in a publication by
Broecker and Peng. As conventionalized model metaphor1, the conveyor belt is
part of an allegory that was made to explain the distribution of nutrients in
the sea.
"The exhibits in a fun house are located on two levels. The upper floor has a
large conveyor belt that moves from right to left; the lower floor, a belt
that moves from left to right. Those who enter are free to observe the
horrors in any order they wish. There are innumerable escalators from the
lower to the upper level. However, there is only one escalator from the upper
to the lower level, located at the end of the upper belt. Those who venture
to the upper level are harassed by monsters lurking in dark alcoves. These
monsters grab the unsuspecting visitors and, after a suitable frightening,
drop them through holes to the lower level. The average fun-seeker has to
ride to the upper level many times to view all its mysteries before leaving
the fun house."
This text can be classified as an allegory in a pedagogical context because
later on it is explicitly explained that "the fun-seeker is the limiting
nutrient and the monster is the plant. The belts and escalators represent
the organized flow of water, and the wandering of the people is the turbulent
mixing superimposed on this organized flow." The text contains a whole field
of different metaphors, but only the conveyor belt metaphor has further
importance later on.
Following Peirce, the metaphor "the ocean is a conveyor belt" can be
interpreted as a parallelism predicate that contains two incompatible
meanings:
The ocean is (an ocean || a conveyor belt).
For the interpretation of this metaphor, first the qualities of both
predicates (Max Black speaks of 'associated commonplaces') are developed
separately. The meaningful structures are set into relation to each other.
The conveyor belt structure is the diagram of the ocean current structure.
For the interpretation of the metaphor the differences rather than the
similarities between the structure of the diagram and the diagrammed subject
are important. One difference is, for example, the current's quality "to
consist of water" and the conveyor's quality "that it is used to manufacture
technical mass products". Together with similarities like "has a closed
circulation" or "is used as a transport system", differences are always
activated. They warn of unjustified similarities. Furthermore, 'conveyor
belt' works as a deepening metaphor. It has a simpler structure than
'current' and makes the complicated pattern of ocean currents more
understandable. Therefore, it is important for the use of the metaphor in the
pedagogical context of the allegory of (Broecker and Peng 1982)1982.
However, two years later it becameomes important as a research guiding tool.
That leads us to:
3.2.2 Step II) model metaphor1 restored to life as emphatical remainder
metaphor2
In 1984 Broecker succeeded in including North Atlantic deep water production
in the global climate context. In doing this, he inspired a new field of
research. The starting point came from the results of experiments in
Greenland that he could connect to his work on ocean currents. Broecker
explained the circumstances under which that he realized the importance of
deep water production: "In 1984 after listening to a lecture by Hans Oeschger
in Bern, Switzerland, he pointed out that Greenland's core records suggested
millennial duration oscillations between two states of climate."
Oeschger had measured the CO2 content of air, a signal preserved in the
Greenland glaciers that indicated CO2 fluctuations throughout the paleo
record. With the differences in the ice levels, it was possible to identify
oscillations between two global climatic states of climate. However, an
explanation for these two different states was not clear. "A few days later
it popped into my head that these two states could be North Atlantic Deep
Water production 'on' and 'off'."
For Broecker's findings, it was necessary to a) identify the relevance of
North Atlantic deep water production and b) realize the possibility of two
different ocean current states and their association with two different
climatic states.
a) To establish the relevance of North Atlantic deep water production
Broecker emphasized the importance of the conveyor belt. In the industrial
world, the introduction of the conveyor belt in factories greatly increased
productivity and had a major impact on economic development. In a similar
way, Broecker realized the importance of the conveyor belt in deep water
production. "Its flow is equal to that of 100 Amazon Rivers and is similar in
magnitude to all the planet's rainfall. This came out of a knowledge of the
strength of this conveyor flow based on C14 measurements I made as part of my
thesis research."
For getting his second idea, two different research interests were necessary
to combine as Broecker (1997) described:
"I had known about this because my career has had a dual aspect. One part of
it involved a study of the ocean's deep circulation by means of radiocarbon
and other tracers. The focus was to try to understand how rapidly fossil-fuel
CO2 would be absorbed into the ocean. The other aspect involved studies of
paleoclimate. I was captivated by the observation that each of the major
100,000-yr-duration glacial cycles that have hounded us during the past
million years came to a catastrophic close. So in 1984, I realized that I
could merge these two studies and ask the question, 'What would happen if
this major current were to be shut off or turned down?'"
b) The possibility of two different ocean current states had to be realized
and identified with the different climatic states obtained from the ice core
records. All climate models with that Broecker was acquainted at that time
were only concerned with present day ocean circulation. Nevertheless,
Broecker had the idea that a different mode without deepwater production was
possible. The 'on' and 'off' states of deepwater production were activated by
the conveyor belt's 'on' and 'off' operation modes. While working out his
concept, Broecker recognized the possibility of a third mode of operation
corresponding to the direction of deep water flow during the Ice Age which
was probably different from that of today. And indeed, numerical modeling
studies (Bryan, 1986; Manabe and Stouffer, 1988) confirm this idea of
multiple equilibria of the oceanic circulation.
The finding of the connection between states of deep water production and
global climate is an example for the creative potential of metaphor by
pointing to differences rather than similarities.
Let us now turn to the restoration of model metaphor1 as emphatical remainder
metaphor2: After 1982, the conventionalized model metaphor1 was no longer
emphatical. Therefore, the differences between an ocean current and a
conveyor belt would no longer be well shown with this metaphor. Consequently,
the conveyer belt's quality of having different states became irrelevant
under the model's standard interpretation. Thus, model metaphor1 no longer
focused on that difference.
In 1984, the metaphor reappeared as emphatical remainder metaphor2 and the
quality of having different states was vitalized. This became a key to the
interpretation of climate records from glacial times.
This example makes clear that besides the normal development of a metaphor
from an emphatical to a lexical metaphor via a conventionalized model
metaphor, a reverse step is also possible.
While refining his concept, Broecker realized that others would consider the
possibility that different modes of circulation existed, and could have an
impact on global climate. As early as 1906, T.C. Chamberlin published these
ideas in an article with the title "On a Possible Reversal of Deep-Sea
Circulation and its Influence on Geologic Climates". He was the first to
systematically connect oscillating climate states with different modes of
currents.
"The climatic student seems therefore compelled to face oscillations within
the known geologic periods, ranging from sub-tropical congeniality within the
polar circles, on the one hand, to glacial conditions in low latitudes, on
the other, and these in alternating succession; while neither of these
oscillations was permitted to swing across the narrow limital lines of
organic endurance. There is little doubt that the ocean, the daughter of the
atmosphere, is one of the most potential agencies in controlling these
oscillations. It is one of its possible functions in such regulation that
invites our present attention."
Chamberlin's central idea was the possibility of a reverse current operation
mode. He realized that the agencies that influenced the deep-sea movements in
opposite phases were nearly balanced.
"From this sprang the suggestion that, if their relative values were changed
to the extent implied by geological evidence, there might be a reversal of
the direction of the deep-sea circulation, and that this might throw light on
some of the strange climatic phenomena of the past and give us a new means of
forecasting of climatic states in the future."
Independently from Chamberlin, Stommel (1961) developed from a theoretical
point of view a model from a theoretical point of view that indicated that
the ocean must have different modes of operation, but he did not connect this
idea with climate records. This connection was realized by Rooth (1982) in a
similar model, without knowing the ideas of Chamberlin and Stommel.
The fact that none of these authors used the conveyor belt metaphor
(Stommel's model does not rest on any metaphor at all) indicates that neither
a special metaphor nor metaphorical reasoning in general was necessary to
discover the connections.
However, it is interesting that Chamberlin also used a metaphor for
describing the importance of the ocean current too: "the ocean, the daughter
of the atmosphere". An investigation of this metaphor can not be done in this
paper, but such an approach is valuable, because in the first decades of this
century oceanography followed was strongly influenced by the field of
meteorology.
3.2.3 Step III) communication of the conventionalized model metaphor3
It is striking that after 1982 the conveyor belt metaphor was not mentioned
again in the literature until 1987. Although the conveyor belt metaphor
played an outstanding role in Broecker's findings, the metaphor is not
mentioned in any of his publications from 1984 and 1985. A reason for that
could be the emphatical structure of the metaphor. This irreplaceability goes
hand in hand with the creative potential of the metaphor, but also with its
typical resistance and scandalous nature. As long as the metaphor is
emphatic, its absurdity is still recognized and the objection is always
included: "The ocean current is obviously not a conveyor belt!" With the
progress of conventionalizing, model metaphor3 is less and less scandalous.
Consequently, the conveyor belt metaphor appears again in Broecker's
publications after 1987. With lexical proscription the metaphor completely
loses its resistance. An example for such a metaphor is the electron cloud in
physics. The conveyor belt metaphor has not yet reached this stage, and
speaking of a final stage would not be appropiateccurate as every lexicalized
metaphor can be revitalized at any time.
Broecker's publication in 1987 gives a detailed description of his developed
model2. This time the conveyor belt metaphor has the function of presenting
his model to a wider circle of readers outside the geoscience community.
Included is a large logo of the conveyor's structure covering two pages (cf.
Fig. 2). In this form, Broecker's model became much better known, and was
partly used as the logo of the organization "Global Change Research
Initiative".
Readers without a background knowledge of oceanography may have problems
understanding Broecker's metaphor. Laypeople may transfer qualities of the
conveyor belt to this model that experts know to be inappropriate. Broecker
(1991, p. 79) mentions about his logo, "that it implies that if one were to
inject a tracer substance into one of the conveyor's segments it would
travel around the loop as a neat package eventually returning to its starting
point." Because of complicated mixing processes this does not happen.
Following Peirce, building a metaphor is a process of communication.
Important is the knowledge that shared by author and interpreter have in
common. Besides simple misunderstanding that can disturb the communication,
something like a creative misunderstanding can also happen. An example for
that is again Broecker's 1987 text. Broecker (1991, p. 88) writes about his
communication with the editor of this publication:
"the editor put a sales 'stimulator' on the cover that stated 'Europe beware:
the big chill may be coming.' At the time I was much annoyed because no
mention of the conveyor's future was made in the article. To make matters
worse, even after reading the article itself, many people were left with the
impression that I was warning of an imminent conveyor shutdown. The fact is
that I thought, at that time, that the coming greenhouse warming would, if
anything, strengthen the conveyor by increasing the rate of vapor loss from
the Atlantic basin. I had not given serious thought to the question as to
whether any changes associated with human's (sic) activities might threaten
the conveyor."
The editor and some readers connect Broecker's model with the future of
global climate. In this case the model metaphor contains more than the author
had intended originally. The final interpretation appears to be creative and
invites Broecker to check its relevance. Broecker changed his mind and ten
years later wrote that the transfer the editor had done the first time was
something normala natural extension of the model: "The question naturally
arises as to whether this finding about past climates has any implications
for the future. I think it does."
The connection with the future became apparent with fruitful consequences. It
was followed by an intensive scientific discussion about the stability of
today's and future deepwater production.
4 Concluding Remarks
We have explored that the very different ways in that metaphor can work
within science. We think that it is necessary to differentiate between
distinct kinds of metaphor to analyze their role in model and theory
development. In Peirce's model of emphatical metaphor the differences between
subject and diagram of the metaphor are at least as important as the
similarities. For the conveyor belt metaphor in the field of oceanography, we
show that the emphatical remainder metaphor provides a fundamental tool to
develop scientific models. The creative potential of the remainder metaphor
is especially helpful in the first stage of theory when other heuristic tools
are not available. Therefore, we think that the application of remainder
metaphors to other case studies in science would be very promising to be left to
furthering investigations.
5 Bibliography
M. Black: 1954, Metaphor. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 55: pp.
273-294
W. S. Broecker: 1987, The biggest chill. Natural History 97 (2): pp. 74-82
W. S. Broecker: 1991, The great ocean conveyor. Oceanography 4 (2): pp. 79-89
W. S. Broecker: 1997, Will Our Ride into the Greenhouse Future be a Smooth
One? GSA Today 7 (5): pp. 1-7; Internet Edition: pp. 1-12
(http://www.geosociety.org/pubs/gsatoday/gsat9705.htm)
W. S. Broecker and T.-S. Peng: 1982, Tracers in the sea. Eldigio press,
Palisades, NY
W. S. Broecker and T. Takahashi: 1984, Is there a Tie between Atmospheric CO2
and Ocean Circulation? In J. E. Hansen (ed.): Climate Progress and Climate
Sensitivity. Geophysical Monograph, New York, pp. 314-326
W. S. Broecker et al.: 1985, Does the ocean-atmosphere system have more than
one stable mode of operation? Nature 315: pp. 21-26
R. Br?ning: 1999, Entstehung des Neuen: Peirce Konzept der Abduktion, das
allgemeine Korrespondenzprinzip und Metaphern in der Wissenschaft.
Historische Fallstudie: Die F?rderbandmetapher in der Ozeanographie.
MK-Verlag, M?ckm?hl
F. Bryan: 1986, High latitude salinity effects and inter-hemispheric
thermohaline circulations. Nature 323: pp. 301-304
T.C. Chamberlin: 1906, On a possible reversal of deep-sea circulation and its
influence on geologic climates. The Journal of Geology July-August: pp.
363-373
A. L. Gordon: 1986, Interocean exchange of thermocline water. Geophys. Res.
91 (C4): pp. 5037-5046
A. von Humboldt: 1814, Voyage aux r=E9gions =E9quinoxiales du nouveau continent.
English translation, H. M. Williams, London, vol. 1, pp. 60-69
E. von Lenz: 1847a, Report on ocean temperatures in different depth. Bulletin
de la Classe Physico-Mathematique de l'Academie des Sciences de
Saint-Petersbourg, 3 Suppl.: pp. 11-12
E. von Lenz: 1847b, Bemerkungen ?ber die Temperatur des Weltmeeres in
verschiedenen Tiefen. Bulletin de la Classe Physico-Mathematique de
l'Academie des Sciences de Saint-Petersbourg 5: pp. 67-74
S. Manabe and R. J. Stouffer: 1988, Two stable equilibria of a coupled
ocean-atmosphere model. J. Climate 1: pp. 841-863
A. Merz and G. W?st: 1922, Die atlantische Vertikalzirkulation. Zeitschr.
Ges. f. Erdkunde: pp. 1-35
A. I. Miller: 1995, Imagery and metaphor: The cognitive science connection.
In Z. Radman (ed): From a metaphorical point of view: A multidisciplinary
approach to the cognitive context of metaphor. De Gruyter, Berlin, pp. 199-224
C. S. Peirce: 1974, Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Volume I-VI,
C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss (ed), Belknap Press of Havard University Press,
Cambridge, Mass.
C. S. Peirce: 1979, Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Volume
VII-VIII, A. W. Burks (ed), Belknap Press of Havard University Press,
Cambridge, Mass.
S. Rahmstorf: 1999, Shifting seas in the greenhouse? Nature 399: pp. 523-524
C. Rooth: 1982, Hydrology and Ocean Circulation. Prog. Oceanog. 11: pp.
131-149
B. Count of Rumford: 1800, Essay VII, The propagation of heat in fluids. In
J. Cadell and W. Davies (ed): Essays, political, economical, and
philosophical, a new Edition, 2, London, pp. 197-386
H. Stommel: 1961, Thermohaline convection with two stable regimes of flow.
Tellus 13: pp. 224-230
C. Strub: 1991, Kalkulierte Absurdit=E4ten. Alber, Freiburg
C. Strub: 1994, Peirce ?ber Metaphern. In H. Pape (ed): Kreativit=E4t und
Logik, Charles S. Peirce und das philosophische Problem des Neuen. Frankfurt
a.M., pp. 209-232
B. A. Warren and C. Wunsch: 1981, Evolution of Physical Oceanography, MIT
Press, Cambridge
G. W?st: 1935, Die Stratosph=E4re des Atlantischen Ozeans. Wiss. Erg. d. D. A.
E. 'Meteor' 1925-1927, 6, (2): pp. 1-288
Vitae/biography
Reinhart Br?ning, born 1965 in Bad Oldesloe, Germany studied physics
and philosophy at Marburg University. After his physics
diploma in 1992, he studied Philosophy of Science at the University of
Konstanz.
He works as science journalist since 1996.
In 1999, he completed his Ph.D. work about on creativity in the research
process;: "Entstehung des Neuen: Peirce Konzept der Abduktion, das
allgemeine Korrespondenzprinzip und Metaphern in der Wissenschaft.
Historische Fallstudie: Die F?rderbandmetapher in der Ozeanographie".
MK-Verlag, M?ckm?hl in 1999.
Gerrit Lohmann was born in 1965 in G?ttingen, Germany. He studied physics and mathematics at the Universities of
G?ttingen and Marburg.
He worked as a Scientific and Teaching Assistant in the Department for Statistical Physics
and Mathematics at the University of Marburg. After his Physics Diploma in 1992, Gerrit moved to the research field of Geoscience at the
Alfred-Wegener-Institute for Polar and Marine Research in Bremerhaven
(Germany). In 1993, he participated on a polar expedition on Research vessel "Polarstern". In 1994, he was a Visiting Scientist at the Earth Science
Center, University of Gothenburg (Sweden). Gerrit received his Ph.D.
degree at the University of Bremen (Germany) in 1995 where he presented a thesis in the field of physical oceanography. Since
1996, he works as a Research Assistant at the Max-Planck-Institute for
Meteorology in Hamburg.
He has authored several publications and conference contributions in climate research.